60

I assume the following is true: assuming a fair coin, getting 10 heads in a row whilst tossing a coin does not increase the chance of the next coin toss being a tail, no matter what amount of probability and/or statistical jargon is tossed around (excuse the puns).

Assuming that is the case, my question is this: how the hell do I convince someone that is the case?

They are smart and educated but seem determined not to consider that I might be in the right on this (argument).

kjetil b halvorsen
  • 63,378
  • 26
  • 142
  • 467
user68492
  • 601
  • 1
  • 6
  • 3
  • 15
    What arguments do *they* bring to bear on their position? Maybe you could draw attention to the fact that a coin does not have a memory. (Alternatively, you could teach them by wagering on the next toss and giving them real steep odds - repeat until they have lost a ton of money.) – Stephan Kolassa Feb 09 '15 at 08:22
  • 1
    They know it's a 50/50 proposition and that the coin has no memory, however they are trying to assert that I am denying statistics; that if there have been 10 heads, then the next in the sequence will more likely be a tail because statistics says it will balance out in the end. – user68492 Feb 09 '15 at 08:29
  • 36
    This known as the [Gambler's Fallacy](http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Gambler%27s_fallacy) – Dan Feb 09 '15 at 08:43
  • 1
    This could be of interest: http://arxiv.org/pdf/1501.04242.pdf – Stéphane Laurent Feb 09 '15 at 09:30
  • 6
    If what they're saying is true, you'd have to record every coin flip since the coin was minted to know if it's a "fair coin" – Mikey Mouse Feb 09 '15 at 12:03
  • 1
    Just imagine that before tossing 10 heads, you tossed 1.000.000 tails... Now what do you expect after the 10 heads? – Emond Feb 09 '15 at 13:49
  • 10
    The key here is whether this is a real coin or a hypothetical one. In stats, getting 10 heads means nothing, and the probability of the next one is still 50/50. In real life, flipping 10 heads would have me examining the coin more closely. – anaximander Feb 09 '15 at 14:03
  • Ask them what mechanism they think the coin uses. In fact, how does it even know that it's supposed to behave 50:50? – Nick Cox Feb 09 '15 at 16:52
  • 15
    Pose this question to your friend: suppose we get ten people to each simultaneously flip ten coins *until all ten come up heads*. The moment that happens -- which you could do in less than an hour -- you have an eleventh person flip an eleventh coin. Ask your friend: is that eleventh person more likely to flip tails? If they say yes, then have them explain why people who have a stake in coin flips -- football teams, say -- do not use this technique to change the odds in their favour. If they say no, have them explain what is different between the two scenarios. – Eric Lippert Feb 09 '15 at 17:12
  • 3
    Alternatively: your friend believes that the odds are better of getting tails. Again: get ten friends, flip coins until you get ten heads in a row, and then see how much your friend is willing to bet against your dollar that the next flip is tails. If they genuinely believe that the coin is biased towards tails, they should be willing to bet more than a dollar against your one dollar. Do this often enough and you might be able to take your friend for the price of a cup of coffee in this town. – Eric Lippert Feb 09 '15 at 17:15
  • 1
    I cannot give this as an answer as I do not have enough points on this stack but if there is a human flipping the coin I would clearly bet against your assumption. Coins are generally fair. They might be slightly weighted one side over another but taking the probability of a 50.1% chance over 10 throws to a 50% chance is negligible. Only knowing this snapshot and nothing else I would wager that the person tossing the coin has a habit of doing so a similar way which is not random. In fact I can flip a quarter in the air and get tails 80-90% of the time if I get to toss my way. – blankip Feb 09 '15 at 20:01
  • 1
    If he is convinced. Then loosing some money should help him. When you have throw ten heads in a row bet him $10 the next will also be a head. Because his chances are higher (he thinks he has a higher chance of getting tails) he should give you some odds on the toss 3/1. Eventually he will owe you plenty of money. – Martin York Feb 09 '15 at 21:39
  • As an aside. There's an old saying in gambling circles that you always bet with the run, never against it. Reason being, if you bet with the run you can only lose once. If you bet against it, you can lose over and over waiting for the run to end. – jono Feb 10 '15 at 01:21
  • There are game players who will [roll the ones out](http://www.darthsanddroids.net/episodes/0099.html). They'll roll a die over and over again until they get a streak of ones, then stop as soon as the streak is broken. Now, they figure, that die is statistically unlikely to roll a one! Maybe your friend will find that more absurd. Or you can have them listen to the [Radiolab episode on Stochasticity](http://www.radiolab.org/story/91684-stochasticity/), particularly [their rebuttal of "hot hands" in basketball](http://www.radiolab.org/story/91687-seeking-patterns/). – Schwern Feb 10 '15 at 05:41
  • If you ask about 2 coin flips and ask your friend to assign probabilities to the combinations: HH, HT, TH, TT, what numbers does he pick? – Ben Aaronson Feb 10 '15 at 16:49
  • 2
    Bring your friend two identical coins. Tell them that one coin just flipped Heads 10x in a row, while the other coin flipped 5 Heads and 5 Tails. Now, they can run any tests they want, and they have to tell you which coin is which. If they are right, then there is a way to tell the coins apart. If "science" is right, the coins are still identical. – abelenky Feb 10 '15 at 18:37
  • You can explain that a coin has a very short memory :-) – user3326185 Feb 11 '15 at 01:00
  • 1
    Make a few quadrillion tosses and you'll find numerous instances of 10 heads in a row. Look at the toss immediately following those 10, and you'll _probably_ find just about half heads and half tails. The odds of 10 heads plus 1 head is equal to the odds of 10 heads plus 1 tail. – user2338816 Feb 11 '15 at 02:47
  • Heck, don't try to convince them, take advantage of them!! – Daniel R Hicks Feb 11 '15 at 19:29
  • 1
    How many of you have seen a 'fair' coin? Someone already mentioned the Gambler's Fallacy I figured I'd throw in the Frictionless Plane Fallacy. Ten flips in a row might not be *that* statistically uncommon but its uncommon enough to make one *question the underlying assumption* (i.e. that the coin is fair). I think that's what your friend is really getting at, even if they're not versed enough in logic to put it that way. – Jared Smith Feb 11 '15 at 20:07
  • I know smart and educated people who claimed that chance of Spain winning the world cup 2014 was close to nil because it (winning 4 major evens in a row) has never happened before. It is the same fallacy! – Akavall Feb 12 '15 at 01:39
  • 3
    If you've just flipped 10 heads in a row, it is not reasonable to assume a fair coin. – Robert Feb 12 '15 at 05:53
  • I would bet on heads just like I always predict the same weather for tomorrow as it is today, which works perfectly until it changes, which happens less often than it not changing. Given that the coin seems to like heads, and there's no statistical difference between choosing heads over tails or vice versa I'd be minded to take advantage of the repetition. You could pose the same question here but instead of ten heads in a row suppose it was 20. 50. 100. 1000. Assuming you can detect nothing amiss with the coin, and you're not dreaming, why would you pick tails for the 1001th coin toss? – bye Feb 12 '15 at 12:27
  • Small pracital note here: The strongest bias in coinflips can be introduced by technique, not by the coin itself. As such, think twice before putting money against the person flipping the coin. – Dennis Jaheruddin Feb 12 '15 at 13:16
  • @Akavall sporting events do not have the presumption of independence between events. Although everything that's happened at one point in time 'never happened before', in sports winning a championship usually *decreases* your odds of winning it again for several reasons: other teams adjust to your tactics/personnel, many sports have salary caps that effectively punish winners, if the sport has a draft those usually punish winners, etc. – Jared Smith Feb 12 '15 at 13:31
  • You could always just understand his misunderstanding and explain it to him that way. The probability of flipping 11 of the same side in a row is extremely low - 1 in 1024. This may be what he is thinking of. However if you've already flipped 10 heads in a row, then "1 in 512" of that work is already done - you've conquered the improbability of the difficult part and all that's left to do is the easy part, i.e. 1 in 1024 (initial prob) divided by 512 (already done) = 1 in 2. – colmde Feb 12 '15 at 14:20
  • The tendency to "balance out" has nothing to do with the coin remembering what came before and trying to cancel it out, it's just simply that with enough coin flips (e.g. 1000), that 10-in-a-row will become insignificant without the need for a 10 tails in a row. – colmde Feb 12 '15 at 14:25
  • @user68492, I'm probably the only one who agrees with you here :) see my answer – Aksakal Feb 12 '15 at 22:22
  • Ob.ref. [Rosencrantz and Guildenstern Are Dead](https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Rosencrantz_and_Guildenstern_Are_Dead): The play opens with Rosencrantz and Guildenstern betting on coin flips. Rosencrantz, who bets heads each time, wins ninety-two flips in a row. The extreme unlikeliness of this event according to the laws of probability leads Guildenstern to suggest that they may be "within un-, sub- or supernatural forces". – Mark Booth Sep 20 '16 at 10:42

13 Answers13

78

they are trying to assert that [...] if there have been 10 heads, then the next in the sequence will more likely be a tail because statistics says it will balance out in the end

There's only a "balancing out" in a very particular sense.

If it's a fair coin, then it's still 50-50 at every toss. The coin cannot know its past. It cannot know there was an excess of heads. It cannot compensate for its past. Ever. it just goes on randomly being heads or tails with constant chance of a head.

If $n_H$ is the number of heads in $n=n_H+n_T$ tosses ($n_T$ is the number of tails), for a fair coin, $n_H/n_T$ will tend to 1, as $n_H+n_T$ goes to infinity .... but $|n_H-n_T|$ doesn't go to 0. In fact, it also goes to infinity!

That is, nothing acts to make them more even. The counts don't tend toward "balancing out". On average, imbalance between the count of heads and tails actually grows!

Here's the result of 100 sets of 1000 tosses, with the grey traces showing the difference in number of head minus number of tails at every step.

enter image description here

The grey traces (representing $n_H-n_T$) are a Bernoulli random walk. If you think of a particle moving up or down the y-axis by a unit step (randomly with equal probability) at each time-step, then the distribution of the position of the particle will 'diffuse' away from 0 over time. It still has 0 expected value, but its expected distance from 0 grows as the square root of the number of time steps. [Note for anyone thinking "is he talking about expected absolute difference or the RMS difference" -- actually either: for large $n$ the first is $\sqrt{2/\pi}\approx$ 80% of the second.]

The blue curve above is at $\pm \sqrt{n}$ and the green curve is at $\pm 2\sqrt{n}$. As you see, the typical distance between total heads and total tails grows. If there was anything acting to 'restore to equality' - to 'make up for' deviations from equality - they wouldn't tend to typically grow further apart like that. (It's not hard to show this algebraically, but I doubt that would convince your friend. The critical part is that the variance of a sum of independent random variables is the sum of the variances $<$see the end of the linked section$>$ -- every time you add another coin flip, you add a constant amount onto the variance of the sum... so variance must grow proportionally with $n$. Consequently the standard deviation increases with $\sqrt{n}$. The constant that gets added to variance at each step in this case happens to be 1, but that's not crucial to the argument.)

Equivalently, $\frac{|n_H-n_T|}{n_H+n_T}$ does go to $0$ as the total tosses goes to infinity, but only because $n_H+n_T$ goes to infinity a lot faster than $|n_H-n_T|$ does.

That means if we divide that cumulative count by $n$ at each step, it curves in -- the typical absolute difference in count is of the order of $\sqrt{n}$, but the typical absolute difference in proportion must then be of the order of $1/\sqrt{n}$.

enter image description here

That's all that's going on. The increasingly-large* random deviations from equality are just "washed out" by the even bigger denominator.

* increasing in typical absolute size

See the little animation in the margin, here

If your friend is unconvinced, toss some coins. Every time you get say three heads in a row, get him or her to nominate a probability for a head on the next toss (that's less than 50%) that he thinks must be fair by his reasoning. Ask for them to give you the corresponding odds (that is, he or she must be willing to pay a bit more than 1:1 if you bet on heads, since they insist that tails is more likely). It's best if it's set up as a lot of bets each for a small amount of money. (Don't be surprised if there's some excuse as to why they can't take up their half of the bet -- but it does at least seem to dramatically reduce the vehemence with which the position is held.)

[However, all this discussion is predicated on the coin being fair. If the coin wasn't fair (50-50), then a different version of the discussion - based around deviations from the expected proportion-difference would be required. Having 10 heads in 10 tosses might make you suspicious of the assumption of p=0.5. A well tossed coin should be close to fair - weighted or not - but in fact still exhibit small but exploitable bias, especially if the person exploiting it is someone like Persi Diaconis. Spun coins on the other hand, may be quite susceptible to bias due to more weight on one face.]

Glen_b
  • 257,508
  • 32
  • 553
  • 939
  • 4
    For the bet proof, perhaps get 2 £/$ (whatever you use) in 1p/1cent coins. Do the betting as mentioned above, with his requested odds based on the likelihood of the previous bets, until one of you has all of the other's money. Once you have taken his money 100 times, it's harder for him to argue. – Jon Story Feb 09 '15 at 14:03
  • 1
    +1 for the bet idea. Losing money seems like a convincing argument... – Erel Segal-Halevi Feb 10 '15 at 17:34
  • 2
    Just a small comment regarding your last statement (in []). According to Andrew Gelman, there [is no such thing as an unfair coin](http://www.stat.columbia.edu/~gelman/research/published/diceRev2.pdf). – Henrik Feb 10 '15 at 20:33
  • @Henrik, I already link *to that article* in my post. You might like to check the other link in the sentence in which I link to it. You may find it quite instructive. While *coins* may (in the very particular sense Gelman intends) be "fair", in another sense (to my recollection, a sense which Diaconis is quite able to exploit repeatedly in demonstrations - being a skilled magician as well as a statistician) the outcome of tossing it may be quite some way from fair. – Glen_b Feb 10 '15 at 21:46
  • @Henrik see [here](https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=ZdA7TeoZD_g), from 2 minutes in. – Glen_b Feb 10 '15 at 21:55
  • @Glen_b Sorry for not realizing that you are actually linking to the Gelman paper. And although the video of Diaconis is pretty awesome, Gelman's arguments probably holds that a *biased coin* does not exist (this does obviously not exclude the possibility of a *biased tosser*). But I am probably splitting hairs here... – Henrik Feb 10 '15 at 22:26
  • @Henrik Gelman's point is you can't bias it by *weighting the coin*. That doesn't imply that the process of tossing can't yield bias. The paper above on which Diaconis is a coauthor (and [this](http://www.smithsonianmag.com/science-nature/gamblers-take-note-the-odds-in-a-coin-flip-arent-quite-5050-145465423/?no-ist) short article) point out that (without a skilled human), a tossed coin is actually slightly (~51:49) more likely to come up the same side as was facing up when it was flipped. So coin tossing is *not* fair; Gelman should really have addressed Diaconis' work in his article. ... ctd – Glen_b Feb 10 '15 at 22:31
  • (ctd) ... While he could not refer to the specific paper I linked to (since it is after Gelman & Nolan; indeed Gelman & Nolan is in the references of Diaconis et al), Diaconis has been discussing this issue for some time. I should go back and put full references in. – Glen_b Feb 10 '15 at 22:38
  • 2
    Lovely answer. A point to note in passing is that the maximum expected "run" in $n$ tosses is $\sqrt n$. 10 in a row in 100 tosses is about right, for 1000 tosses we should expect more than 30 in a row – Dale M Feb 12 '15 at 11:54
  • I think it would be more helpful if in your first plot you could highlight all of the sequences that reach particular extreme level of disproportion (in either direction) and then show that they continue to exhibit Brownian behavior.) There is no balancing. The long-term expectation is NOT that sequences will "balance out but rather that they will "ignore" any past extremes and will have evennees going forward rather than returning to 50/50. – DWin Feb 12 '15 at 17:11
  • @DWin ... Excellent idea, thanks. I'll look at doing something along those lines. – Glen_b Feb 12 '15 at 20:52
  • This is only if it's a fair coin toss. If you see a significant pattern, then it may in fact not be a fair coin toss. If that is so, then it's actually more likely to turn the same face again than the other. In other words, the exact opposite result of what "common sense" would have you believe. – Horse SMith Feb 14 '15 at 14:51
  • @HorseSMith Since the question clearly specifies that a fair coin is to be assumed right at the start, I don't regard it as necessary to restate that the answer assumes it; of course if one changes the condition of the question the answer would differ. – Glen_b Feb 14 '15 at 21:42
  • Is the cumulative proportions essentially the derivative of cumulative heads count? – JobHunter69 Jul 28 '16 at 05:15
  • @Goldname No. The first plot is $n_H-n_T$, and the second plot is that difference divided by the number of tosses, which is the proportion of heads minus the proportion of tails. – Glen_b Jul 28 '16 at 05:19
32

The confusion is because he is looking at the probability from the start without looking at what else has already happened.

Lets simplify things:

First flip:

T

Now the chance of a T was 50%, so 0.5.

The chance that the next flip will be T again is 0.5

TT 0.5
TF 0.5

However, what about the first flip? If we include that then:

TT 0.25
TF 0.25

The remaining 50% is starting with F, and again has an even split between T and F.

To extend this out to ten tails in a row - the probability that you already got that is 1/1024.

The probability that the next one is T or F is 50%.

So the chance from the start of 11 tails is 1 in 2048. The probability that having already flipped tail 10 times that the next flip will also be a tail though is still 50%.

They are trying to apply the unlikeliness of the 1 in 1024 odds of 10 T to the chance of another T, when in fact that has already happened so the probability of it happening is no longer important.

11 tails in a row are no more or less likely than 10 tails followed by one head.

The probability that 11 flips are all tails is unlikely but since it has already happened it doesn't matter any more!

Tim B
  • 421
  • 3
  • 6
13

The odds are still 50-50 that the next flip will be tails.

Very simple explanation: The odds of flipping 10 heads + 1 tail in that order are very low. But by the time you've flipped 10 heads, you've already beaten most of the odds... you have a 50-50 chance of finishing the sequence with the next coin flip.

James K
  • 139
  • 2
12

You should try convincing them that if the previous results were to impact the upcoming tosses then not only the last 10 tosses should have been taken into consideration, but also every previous toss in the coin life.

I think it's a more logical approach.

Arthur Rizzo
  • 221
  • 2
  • 7
  • 1
    This. Common sense is the best way to explain the Gambler's Problem, as common sense is the cause. Start your rebuttal with something like this answer, and they will quickly come to the conclusion that they're wrong on their own. Then they'll be fully receptive to the correct reasoning. – talrnu Feb 10 '15 at 17:27
  • 1
    Why just that coin? Why not every coin ever tossed? – colmde Feb 12 '15 at 14:13
8

To add to earlier answers, there are two issues here, first, what happens when the count is actually fair and each toss is independent of all other tosses. Then, we have the "law of large numbers", saying that in the limit of an ever increasing sequence of tosses, the frequency of tails will approach probability of tail, that is, $1/2$.

If the first ten tosses all were tails, then the limiting frequency will still be one half, without any need of later tosses "balancing out" the first ten tails! Algebraically , let $x_n$ be the number of tails among the throws $11, 12, \dots, n+10.$. Lets assume that actually we get $$ \lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} x_n/n =1/2 $$ Then when taking into account the first ten tosses, we will still have the limit $$ \lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} \frac{10+x_n}{n+10}= 1/2 $$ That is, after one million and ten tosses, we have that $$ \frac{10+500000}{1000010} \approx 0.5 $$ so, in the limit, the first 10 tails doesn't matter at all, its effect is "washed out" by all the later tosses. So, there is no need of "balancing out" for the limit result to hold. Mathematically, this is just using the fact that the limit (if exists ...) of any sequence of numbers do not depend at all on any finite, initial segment! So we can arbitrarily assign the results for the first ten (or first hundred) tosses without affecting the limit, at all. I guess this way of explaining it to your gambler friends (maybe with more numbers & examples and less algebra ...) might be the best way.

The other aspect is: After ten tosses ten tails, maybe somebody starts to doubt if the coin is a good one, corresponds to the simple, ordinary model of independent, equal probability tosses. Assuming the "tosser" (the person doing the tossing) haven't been trained to control the tosses in some way, and is really tossing in a honest way, the probability of tail must be one half (see this Gelman paper.)

So then there must be, in the alternative hypothesis, some dependence among the coin tosses! And, after seeing ten tails in a row, the evidence is that the dependence is a positive one, so that one tail increases the probability that the next coin toss will be tail. But then, after that analysis, the reasonable conclusion is that the probability of the eleventh toss being a tail, is increased, not lowered! So the conclusion, in that case, is the opposite of your gamblers friends.

I think you will need a very strange indeed model to justify their conclusions.

kjetil b halvorsen
  • 63,378
  • 26
  • 142
  • 467
7

This isn't really an answer - your problem is psychological, not mathematical. But it may help.

I often face your "how the hell ..." question. The answers here - mostly correct, are too mathematical for the people you're addressing. One place I start is to try to convince them that flipping one coin 10 times is essentially the same as flipping 10 coins simultaneously. They can grasp the fact that sometimes you'll see 10 heads. In fact that happens about once in a thousand tries (since $2^{10} \approx 10^3$). If 15,000 people try this then about 30 of them will think they have special coins - either all heads or all tails. If they accept this argument then the step to sequential tosses is a little easier.

Ethan Bolker
  • 246
  • 2
  • 7
4

Assuming coin flips are independent, this is very easy to prove from one statistician to another. However, your friend seems to not believe that coin flips are independent. Other than throwing around words that are synonymous with independent (for example, the coin doesn't have a "memory") you can't prove to him that coin flips are independent with a mere word argument. I would suggest using simulation to assert your claim but, to be honest, if your friend doesn't believe coin flips are independent I'm not sure he'll believe simulation results.

TrynnaDoStat
  • 7,414
  • 3
  • 23
  • 39
4

To restate some of the explanations already given (by @TimB and @James K), once you've flipped a coin 10 times and got 10 heads, the probability of getting 10 heads in a row is exactly 1.0! It's already happened, so the probability of that happening is now fixed.

When you multiply that by the probability of getting heads on your next flip (0.5), you get exactly 0.5.

Betting on tails with anything other than even odds at that point is a sucker's bet.

Terry L.
  • 141
  • 2
4

Let's say I'm convinced that the coin is fair. If the coin was fair then the probability of having 10 heads in a row is $$p_{10}=\left(\frac{1}{2}\right)^{10}=\frac{1}{1024}<0.1\%$$ So, as a frequentist at $\alpha=1\%$ significance, I must reject the $H_0$:coin is fair, and conclude that the $H_a$: "something's fishy" is true. No, I can't insist that the probability to see another head is still $\frac{1}{2}$

I'll leave it to you to apply Bayesian approach and get to a similar conclusion. You'll start with prior probability of heads $p=\frac{1}{2}$, then update it with observation of 10 heads in a row, and you'll see how posterior probability of heads $\pi>\frac{1}{2}$

UPDATE @oerkelens example can be interpreted in two ways.

  • your friend bet on THHTTHTTHT, then tossed a coin 10 times and got: THHTTHTTHT. In this case you'll be as surprised as with 10 heads in a row, and start doubting the fairness of a coin. You're not sure what to think about the probability of tail in the next toss, because your friend seems to be able to get exactly what he wants, this is not random.
  • you threw a coin 10 times, and observed some combination which happened to be THHTTHTTHT, you'll notice there were 6 tails and 4 heads, which is $p=\frac{10!}{6!4!2^{10}}\sim 0.2$, which is unremarkable. Hence, the probability of a tail in the next toss is probably $\frac{1}{2}$, since there's no reason to doubt its fairness.

Also, one could argue that although 0.001 is a small probability, if you toss 10 coins 100,000 times, you're bound to see a few 10-head combinations. True, but in this case you have 1 million coin tosses in total, and you're looking for at least one 10-head combination in the sequence. The frequentist probability of observing at least one 10-head combination is computed as follows: $$1-\left(\frac{1}{2^{10}}\right)^{100,000}\approx 1$$ So, the frequentist will conclude after long months of tossing a coin 1 million times and observing a 10-head combination, that it's no big deal, things happen. He will not be making any adjustments to his expectations about the probability of the next head, and leave it at 0.5

FOR COMPUTER PEOPLE If your friends are computer programmers then I found that the easiest way to appeal to their intuition is through programming. Ask them to program the coin toss experiment. They'll think a little bit then come up with something like this:

for i=1:11
   if rand()>0.5 
       c='H';
   else
       c='T';
   end
   fprintf('%s',c)
end
disp '.'

THTHTHTHHHT.

You'll ask them

where's your code for handling 10 heads in a row here? It appears that in your code regardless of what happened in first 10 loops, the 11th toss has 0.5 probability of heads.

However, this case appeals to the fair coin toss. The code is designed with a fair coin toss. In case of 10 heads though, it's highly unlikely that the coin is fair.

Aksakal
  • 55,939
  • 5
  • 90
  • 176
  • But the OP wants to convince his friends, and those friends believe that the chance for another head is _smaller_ than 1/2. – oerkelens Feb 13 '15 at 11:50
  • That's how it is convenient for you to frame and interpret his question. Did you ever see 10 heads in a row with a fair coin? – Aksakal Feb 13 '15 at 11:52
  • 3
    I'm not framing, I'm reading :) The question states: _Does 10 heads in a row increase the chance of the next toss being a tail?_, the Gambler's Fallacy. Your approach is interesting, but does not answer why _in case of a fair coin_ the chances would still be 50/50 :) Considering ever seeing 10 heads in a row with a fair coin, let me ask you if you have ever seen the following series: THHTTHTTHT? Because that is _as_ unlikely as seeing HHHHHHHHHH. Strangely enough, presented with that series, your formula should also decide the coin is unfair. – oerkelens Feb 13 '15 at 11:56
  • @oerkelens, updated my answer to your comment, thanks – Aksakal Feb 13 '15 at 13:37
3

Under ideal circumstances the answer is no. Each throw is independent of what came before. So if this is a truly fair coin then it does not matter. But if you unsure about whether the coin is faulty or not (which could happen in real life), a long sequence of tails may lead one to believe that it is unfair.

Nicolas Bourbaki
  • 1,080
  • 9
  • 22
  • 3
    No, no, no! There is no such a thing as "unfair coin". It is just a statistics handbooks invention. See: http://www.stat.columbia.edu/~gelman/research/published/diceRev2.pdf – Tim Feb 09 '15 at 08:53
  • @Tim What if the coin has both sides heads? More seriously, I understand what you are saying. There are no coins that look genuine but are unbalanced. I did not know that. – Nicolas Bourbaki Feb 09 '15 at 08:56
  • NP, just what am I saying that the coin example is purely theoretical one and should be treated as so. – Tim Feb 09 '15 at 08:59
  • 1
    @Tim Well, I do mathematics, so I do not really care if the concept is realistic! I just pretend there is such a coin for sake of example. But in the future, if I ever have to teach probability theory again, I will tell the students that realistically such coins do not exist. – Nicolas Bourbaki Feb 09 '15 at 09:01
  • @Tim There are plenty of unfair coins. The simplest way is to have a coin with two sides the same and use slight of hand to swap it for a fair one at appropriate moments. Alternatively I imagine you could fit some interesting electronics and mechanics inside a coin to give a more high tech unfair coin. – Tim B Feb 09 '15 at 15:18
  • 1
    @Tim IIRC, there is no such thing as an unfair coin for all practical intents and purposes, however that is not mean that any coin is precisely fair. If you have an infinite sample size, you can detect arbitrarily small "statistically significant" differences, and no real world object ever behaves *exactly* as its theoretical model suggests. – Dikran Marsupial Feb 09 '15 at 15:53
  • 1
    @Tim that reference does not say there is not 'unfair coin', it says specifically in the case of flipping a coin it is not unfair (and even with this, is using a persons hand, not gravity), and it is proven empirically by students flipping coins. The study does not properly compare coin to dice, as it claims dice can be weighted, but does not try flipping them in the hand. – user-2147482637 Feb 10 '15 at 01:20
3

This answer will work for all questions of this sort, including the Monty Hall problem. Simply ask them what they think the odds are of getting a tail after ten heads. Offer to play them for slightly better (to them) but still under 50-50 odds. With any luck they will agree to let a computer do the flipping in which case you will quickly have a sum of money in your pocket. Otherwise it will take longer but the result is (inevitably) the same.

meh
  • 1,902
  • 13
  • 18
  • +1. Of course, first you have to be patient enough to keep flipping the coin until ten heads in a row come up! – whuber Nov 11 '15 at 01:43
  • Yes, and who wants to wait an average of 2046 flips to see that? – soakley Nov 11 '15 at 03:24
  • and that is why i said if he is lucky they will accept computer flips. Nonetheless, it is free money for the believer in MP and a cheap lesson for the non-believer. I certainly never suggested that the op hold his breath waiting for the event. In addition, there is nothing magical about 10, they would have to believe that 9, 8 ,... even 2 heads in a row influence the odds. Now the waiting time to flip coins seems reasonable – meh Nov 11 '15 at 04:00
0

How would you convince them? One way is to show the distribution of outcomes from the exact problem described.

#1,000,000 observations
numObservations <- 1e+6
#11 coin tosses per sample
numCoinTosses <- 11

sampledCoinTosses <- matrix(sample(c(-1,1),numObservations*numCoinTosses,replace=TRUE),
                        nrow = numObservations, ncol = numCoinTosses)
sampledCoinTosses <- cbind(sampledCoinTosses,apply(sampledCoinTosses[,1:numCoinTosses - 1],1,sum))
#Where the sum of the first ten observations is 10, this corresponds to 10 heads.
tenHeadsObservations <- sampledCoinTosses[which(sampledCoinTosses[,numCoinTosses + 1] == 10),]
#By looking at the summary of the 11th coin toss we can see how close the average value is to 0
summary(tenHeadsObservations[,numCoinTosses])
Henry E
  • 344
  • 1
  • 12
-3

Try like this: Assume that we already have $10$ heads tosses -- a very very rare event with probability of "being there" of $0.5^{10}$. Now we prepare for one more toss, and think ahead what might happen next:

  • if tails, we still end up with recording an extremely rare series of events with probability of $0.5^{10}$;
  • if heads, the probability of whole series is somewhat smaller, but not That much smaller, $0.5^{11}$;

And the difference between the two is just one fair coin toss.

coulminer
  • 337
  • 2
  • 8
  • In the first bullet, exactly what is the "event" to which you refer? – whuber Feb 09 '15 at 09:00
  • even of "being there", sorry spotted the typo – coulminer Feb 09 '15 at 09:01
  • 1
    How do you obtain $0.5^{10}$ for a specific sequence of *eleven* tosses? – whuber Feb 09 '15 at 09:29
  • 0.5^10 * 1^1 I just live in the universe where we only care of total heads in a row – coulminer Feb 09 '15 at 10:27
  • I don't understand. After the tenth head, the next toss has 50% chance of landing heads, but you're saying that that is actually a slightly less likely outcome. Is that what you're saying? – Smig Feb 09 '15 at 18:10
  • I am saying that it's always 0.5 to land heads, and 0.5 to land tails. and the "smart and educated" are right in the sense that they gut feel that getting 10 heads in a row is extremely unlikely and probability to get next heads is again lower. – coulminer Feb 10 '15 at 08:10
  • But the dissonance they are experiencing comes from them not accounting for the fact that it does not really matter what we expect on 11th toss, it matters that we expect it or not, i.e what we count as "positive outcome" when estimating the probability as "number of positive outcomes"/"all available outcomes". – coulminer Feb 10 '15 at 08:18